The Premodern Interpretational Approaches to Ethics and Reason in Qur’an and Its Interpretational Implications
Does the Qur’an
advocate ethical subjectivism, ethical objectivism, or
ethical voluntarism ? In other words does the Qur’an
assume that what
is right can always be known by revelation- independent
reason alone ;
what is right can be known in some cases by revelation-
independent reason
alone and in others by revelation and revelation- derived
sources whereby
both of these sources are complementary and in agreement, or in order
to know what is right, humans must always rely only on
revelation and
revelation- derived sources and can never know what is right
by independent
reason.
This leads us into
the widely discussed theme in Islamic tradition of
the nature of the relationship between reason and revelation
(whose exact
relationship is yet to be systematically arrived at.
Elsewhere I demonstrated that the legitimacy and the place
of reason in conceptualizing the nature and the
interpretation of Qur’an
and Sunna during the first three to four generations of
Muslims was much
broader and reason inclusive than in postformative Islamic
thought. I
argued that it was only in the middle of the second century
of the Islamic
calendar that the epistemological- methodological framework
behind the
concept of the nature of the relationship between reason and
revelation
and revelation derived- sources started to initiate the
mechanisms that ultimately
resulted in introducing a qualitative change to the reason-
revelation
dynamic. This change completely subordinated ontologically,
epistemologically,
and methodologically the scope and the legitimacy of reason
and
reason- derived opinion ( ra’y ) to that of the textually
based sources of revelation,
i.e., Qur’an and Hadith. With this process in completion by
the
middle of the third century of the Islamic calendar, reason
was primarily
used in a derivative sense to assist in arriving at the
consensus of opinions
( ijma’ ) of the Muslim Community or in its analogical (
qiyas ) function.
The above described
tendency toward ahistorical, decontextualized,
and philologically oriented manahij to Qur’anic
interpretation was based
upon a particular concept of the nature of the primary
sources of Islamic Weltanschauung . Once Sunna was conceptually equated with
Hadith and
made epistemologically and methodologically dependent upon
canonical
hadith compendia and the hadith- based hermeneutic of the
Qur’an was
elevated to the highest ranks of the interpretational
endeavor, the role of
reason in the overall Qur’anic hermeneutic was relegated to
the background.
The reason- based interpretation had now to function within
the boundaries
of the entirely textually based interpretational framework.
This narrowing
of the interpretational scope of reason was hermeneutically
incapable
of going beyond the text and searching for the possible
moral trajectories,
rationale, and objectives ( maqasid ) of the Qur’anic
revelation.
Furthermore this
manhaj permitted only a derivative use of reason in
the form of an analogy ( qiyas ), which was
epistemologically and methodologically
embedded firmly in the normative textual indicants. The
role of reason, thus, was seen as strictly instrumental. The
Divine Will,
as embodied in the normative texts, was considered by the
majority of
legal philosophers as the sole determinant in the realm of
law and “no
concept of human reason as [being] author of ultimate source
of law”
was developed. Indeed, in the context of characterizing
classical Islamic
law, argues Weiss, that “between human reason and the law of
God there
stretched an essentially unbridgeable gap.” Weiss terms
this hermeneutical
tendency in premodern manahij as voluntarism . It permeated
the way
in which nature of law, ethics, morality, and ontology was
conceptualized.
A subscription to voluntarism has important
interpretational implications.
Firstly, it affects the way in which the nature and the
character of
Qur’anic revelation is perceived and interpreted.
Voluntarism was responsible
for infusing the Revelation with a comprehensive legalistic
ethos and
subsequent marginalization of some of its other dimensions
such as those
that could be broadly termed ethicoreligious in nature. This
distorted the
way in which the overall nature, character, and “purpose” of
the Qur’anic
Revelation and its message were perceived and subsequently
conceptualized.
Voluntarism also implies a legalistic expression of the Will
of God
that can only be known from commands and prohibitions. This
approach
renders the law entirely dependent upon a sovereign and unbound
divine
will that denies any rational element in it as well as views
humanity as not
being capable of comprehending independently of the help of
revelation.
An interpretational model premised on voluntarism also
assumes that the
text includes the complete knowledge and that the role of
reason in interpretation
of the text is minimal. All four Sunni premodern major
schools of
jurisprudence and theology adopted in various degrees a
“voluntarist” view
of the relationship between reason and revelation. As argued
in the second
chapter NTS school of thought went further by even disputing
the legitimacy
of analogical reason in any branches pertaining to ‘ilm may
that be in usul- ul- fiqh or theology.
This voluntaristic hermeneutic, as espoused by the most
widespread theology of Sunni Asha’rism,
is ultimately responsible for the subversion of rational
ethics and authority
in Islamic law and ethics according to which “an act can be
gauged as
good from a certain perspective and detestable from
another,” and “both
analysis would be in accordance with the sovereign will of
God.” Al Attar
describes this view of ethics and morality as being based on
a “Divine
Command Theory,” which presupposes that “divine commands and
rules
have to be obeyed regardless of the social or moral
implications, as there is
no rationale beyond their being divine commands.”
Taken from Chapter 3 of this book ( free PDF).
Comments
Post a Comment